Выбрать главу

Davidson, D., 1980, Essays on Actions and Events, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

Davies, P. S., 2001, Norms of Nature, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

Franssen, M., 2006, The normativity of artifacts, Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 37:42-57.

Franssen, M., 2008, The inherent normativity of functions in biology and technology, in: Functions and More: Comparative Philosophy of Technical Artifacts and Biological Organisms, Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology, U. Krohs and P.A. Kroes, eds., MIT Press, Cambridge, MA., forthcoming.

Houkes, W., 2006, Knowledge of artifact functions, Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 37:102-113.

Houkes, W., Vermaas, P. E., Dorst, C., and de Vries, M. J., 2002, Design and use as plans: an action-theoretic account, Des. Stud. 23:303-320.

Kroes, P., and Meijers, A., 2006, The dual nature of technical artifacts, Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 37:1-4 (introduction to a special issue).

Millikan, R. G., 1984, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

Parfit, D., 1984, Reasons and Persons, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

Preston, B., 1998, Why is a wing like a spoon? a pluralist theory of function., J. Phil. 95:215-254.

Thomasson, A. L., 2003, Realism and human kinds, Phil. Phen. Res. 67:580-609.

Vermaas, P. E., and Houkes, W. N., 2003, Ascribing functions to technical artifacts: a challenge to etiological accounts of functions. Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 54:261-289.

Wouters, A., 2005, The function debate in philosophy, Act. Biotheor. 53:123-151.

Designing is the Construction of Use Plans

Wybo Houkes

Abstract In this chapter, I argue for an intentionalist reconstruction of artifact design, called the “use-plan analysis.” In it, design crucially involves the construction and communication of a use plan. After presenting an outline of the use-plan analysis, I show that it can be used to accommodate four aspects of the phenomenology of artifact use and design: creative use, serendipity, the unread manual, and unknown designers; and I briefly indicate how the analysis facilitates the evaluation of artifact use and design. From this, I conclude that the use-plan analysis provides a phenomenologically viable, evaluatively useful, intentionalist account of use and design.

1 Introduction

Designing is of vital importance for every human society - from early tool-users to heavily technology-dependent contemporary societies. The products of designing range from skyscrapers to microchips and weather satellites to wicker baskets. Yet accounts of design, especially within analytical philosophy, are as rare as Siberian tigers - and not nearly as actively searched out.

In this contribution, I do not aim to set this straight by giving a complete analysis, let alone a clear-cut definition of designing. Instead, I present a framework for understanding at least one important type of designing, namely that of run-of-the-mill consumer utensils, such as cars and toothbrushes. This use-plan analysis starts from the seemingly trivial observation that designing is, like scientific research or swimming, an activity. One may therefore apply to designing resources drawn from one branch of analytical philosophy, namely philosophy of action. This discipline is mainly concerned with understanding intentional actions, i.e., actions that express purposefulness and deliberation.

W. Houkes, Eindhoven University of Technology

P. E. Vermaas et al. (eds.), Philosophy and Design. © Springer 2008

I present in section 2 an analysis of designing, and, more cursorily, using, as an intentional action involving use plans for material objects. Here I aim at clarity and conciseness, not at completeness. Many details of the use-plan analysis, developed in close cooperation with Pieter Vermaas, and of its application are omitted here and can be found elsewhere (Houkes et al., 2002; Houkes and Vermaas, 2004; Vermaas and Houkes, 2006; Houkes and Vermaas, 2006).

The presentation is followed by a preliminary assessment of the use-plan analysis, again aimed at clarity rather than completeness. In section 3, I show how the use-plan analysis provides a phenomenologically viable framework for understanding designing by accommodating four aspects of artifact design and use. These aspects are presented as criticisms, because they appear to offer grounds for objections against the use-plan analysis, and for accepting alternative accounts. I then show the phenomenological mettle of the use-plan analysis by responding to all four criticisms. Some of these responses show, in addition, the primary advantage of the use-plan analysis, namely that it may be employed to evaluate using and designing. In section 4, I briefly sum up these evaluative features, and I conclude that the use-plan analysis provides a phenomenologically viable, evaluatively useful, intentionalist account of designing.

2 The Use-Plan Analysis of Designing

The use-plan analysis of designing is an action-theoretical account developed by Pieter Vermaas and myself and presented in several publications (Houkes et al., 2002; Houkes and Vermaas, 2004; Vermaas and Houkes, 2006; Houkes and Vermaas, 2006).26 Central to this analysis is the notion of a use plan for an artifact: a series of actions, including deliberate manipulations of the artifact which are considered by an agent for achieving a certain goal.

As an example, consider a prototypical designed object or artifact: a car. Driving a car is an activity that is typically purposeful and that always involves several contributory actions. These actions may be rather trivial, such as sitting in the driver’s seat, or relatively complicated, such as operating the clutch. Yet several such actions are involved in driving a car. Moreover, this set of actions is typically structured as an ordering. Some actions, such as fastening one’s seat belt and checking the fuel level, may be taken in any order; other actions, however, such as engaging the clutch and shifting gears, need to be taken in strict succession. Actions when driving a car may be conditional for other actions and conditioned by other actions: one has to open a car door to switch on the radio, which in turn enables the selection of a different radio station. That the actions comprised by driving are structured as orderings, partial or complete, and by conditionals means that driving can be understood in terms of a plan - a structured, temporally extended series of (considered) actions.27 Many plans, but not all, involve deliberate manipulations of material objects other than our own bodies. Such plans may be called use plans for these objects. Thus, the typical series of actions starting with opening a car door and leading to the release of the hand brake may be called the use plan of a car, but also of a car door and a hand brake, and perhaps of the engine and the spark plugs. In contrast, walking through a park may involve a plan, e.g., for meeting people, but analyzing this activity as involving a use plan for the grass would make the notion of a use plan virtually all-encompassing and therefore uninteresting. Whether use plans can be distinguished from plans in general in any precise way need not concern us here.

Of more interest is the source of the structure of use plans: why do some actions in driving a car need to be taken in strict succession, whereas the order of other actions is arbitrary? It may be difficult to recognize this as a genuine question, mainly because the answer is so obvious: if some actions are taken in a different order, one has little hope of achieving the goal of driving one’s car, whereas the order of other actions is irrelevant for achieving this goal. Thus, the structure of the use plan for an artifact ultimately depends on the goal to which using the artifact is supposed to contribute. If you want to use a car for driving, releasing the hand brake at some point, but not too soon, is crucial; if you only want to listen to the car radio in your garage, releasing the hand brake is at best unnecessary.

вернуться

26

The use-plan analysis is similar to at least one characterization found in design methodology (Hubka and Eder, 1998) and resembles others (e.g., Roozenburg and Eekels, 1995). For lack of space, neither these similarities nor the equally significant differences will be discussed here.

вернуться

27

See Bratman (1987) and Pollock (1995) for general action-theoretical analyses of plans.