Выбрать главу

Equality was always a chimera or a lie; separation was real. The

model held that social institutions could be reasonably and fairly

constructed on the basis of biology, for instance, race or skin color.

What made separation necessary—the presumed inferiority of one

of the biologically defined groups—made equality impossible. The

idea of separation and the institutions of separation derived from a

social inequality of such astonishing magnitude and crass cruelty

that separation in idea or practice essentially denied that blacks had

a human nature in common with whites or any common human

standing. The separate-but-equal model itself originates in the conviction that men and women could not stand on common human ground. The model originates in the effort to justify the subordination of women to men (and in the justification to perpetuate that subordination) by positing male and female natures so biologically

different as to require social separation, socially antithetical paths,

social life bifurcated by sex so that there are two cultures, one

male, one female, coexisting in the same society. The separate-but-

equal model applied to sex predated the variation of the model applied to race. With respect to sex, the separate-but-equal model held that women and men were destined by biology for different

social spheres. The spheres were separate but equal, which made

the men and women separate but equal. The sphere of the woman

was the home; the sphere of the man was the world. These were

separate-but-equal domains. The woman was supposed to bear and

raise the children; the man was supposed to impregnate her and

support them. These were separate-but-equal duties. The woman

had female capacities— she was intuitive, emotional, tender,

charming (in women a capacity to arouse or entrap, not an attribute). T he man had male capacities— he was logical, reasoning, strong, powerful (as a capacity and relative to the woman). These

were separate-but-equal capacities. The woman was supposed to

do domestic labor, the precise nature of which was determined by

her husband’s social class. The man was supposed to labor in the

world for money, power, recognition, according to his social class.

This was separate-but-equal labor.

Sex segregation in practice is necessarily different from race segregation: women are everywhere, in almost every home, in most beds, as intim ate as it is possible to be with those who want to keep

them separate. Given the nearly universal intim acy women have

with men, it is astonishing to recognize how successful sex-segre-

gation bolstered by the separate-but-equal model has been and

continues to be. Women have invaded the male sphere of the marketplace, only to be segregated in female job ghettos. In jobs, duties, responsibilities, physical, moral, and intellectual capacities, division of labor within the home, the ethic and practice that still

obtains is sex segregation. The separate-but-equal model applied to

men and women continues to be effective because it is seen to correspond to biology accurately and fairly. The model has credibility because the sexual subordination of women to men is seen to be in

the nature of things and a logical premise of social organization— a

biological reality that is properly reiterated in social institutions,

civil prerogatives, and sex-segregated obligations. The model is

perceived as fair because in it men and women are kept biologically

separate (discrete), socially separate (discrete), and they are declared equal because each is doing equally what is appropriate to

their sex. Separation is seen to be the only real vehicle of equality

for women. The notion is that women competing with men, not

limited to a female sphere, could never achieve social or economic

or sexual equality because of their nature—which in all of these

areas would simply be inferior to male nature; females are inferior,

however, only because they have left the female sphere, which in

itself is equal, not inferior; females are only inferior to men in a

male sphere, where they do not belong. Equality is guaranteed by

setting up separate spheres according to sex and simply insisting

that the spheres are equal. This amounts to a kind of metaphysical

paternalism: constructing a social model in which women need not

experience their inferiority as a burden but instead are assigned

such social value as women that their inferiority is of equal social

worth to the superiority of men. The separate spheres are declared

equal with no reference to the material conditions of the persons in

the spheres and this is the sense in which women have equality

with men under this model. There need not be equality of rights,

for instance; indeed, it is counterindicated. Since the sexes are not

the same, they should not be treated the same, and something is

wrong when a common standard is applied to both. In this social

model, separation by sex class is viewed as the only basis for equality; sex segregation is the institutional expression of this egalitarian ethic, its program in fact. With sex as with race, separation is a

fact; equality is a chimera or a lie.

The woman-superior model of antifeminism is found in two apparently opposing realms: the spiritual and the sexual. In the spiritual realm, the woman is superior to the male by definition; he worships her because she is good; her sex makes her moral or gives

her the responsibility for a morality that is sex-specific. Being

female, she is higher, by nature closer to some abstract conception

of good. She is credited with a moral sensibility that men are hard

put to match (but then, they are not expected to try): she is ethereal, she floats, her moral nature lifts her up, she gravitates toward

that which is pure, chaste, and tasteful. She has an instinctive, sex-

based knowledge of what is good and right. Her moral sensibility

is unfailingly benign, always an influence toward the good. Her

sex-class business includes the business of being virtuous— a

strange assignment by sex, since the Latin root of the word v irtu e

means “strength” or “m anliness, ” which perhaps shows the futility

of the project for her. T his goodness of her sex is essentially based

on a presumed chastity, a necessary chastity— of behavior but also

of appetite. She, as a woman, is not supposed to know sexual desire. Men lust. As one who by her nature does not lust, she is the opposite of man: he is carnal; she is good. There is no notion of

female m orality or of a woman’s being good in the world that is not